In this
paper I will argue that the doctrine of the mean is too demanding, and not
plausible. Using Wolf’s view on moral saints to demonstrate precision, I will
demonstrate Curzer’s view of hitting the mean after which I will show that this
way is too demanding and not plausible. This paper
will then show an objection using phronesis as a plausible way to hit the mean
without being too demanding. I will then respond by saying that
phronesis requires impossible actions, and if this ideal is impossible then it
is too demanding. This paper will then conclude with the results of the paper
by accounting for all of the objections.
There is a
dispute between Hursthouse and Curzer about the interpretation of Aristotle’s
account of what a virtue is. Is it a quantifiable heuristic definition of a
virtue or is it a metaphorical definition with many ways of getting at a
virtue? Aristotle states, “Now virtue is concerned with passions and actions,
in which excess is a form of failure, and so is defect, while the intermediate
is praised and is a form of success; and being praised and being successful are
both characteristics of virtue. Therefore virtue is a kind of mean, since, as
we have seen, it aims at what is intermediate (1106b-25, Ross 1980)
Curzer
argues that Aristotle’s account should be taken literally. “If a quantitative
doctrine of the mean offers a plausible picture of the virtues rather than a
silly picture, then a literal doctrine of the mean is preferable to a
metaphorical, heuristic one.” (Curzer, 129) Curzer accepts that there are many
parameters to hitting the mean. Courage is found exactly between fear and over
confidence, but there are ways to find the mean by hitting it at the right
time, with the right aim, with the right way, and the right thing. Just because
there are multiple ways of being confident, it does not take away from the
doctrine of mean. One must still hit the center of all the fore mentioned
parameters. Curzer also references Aristotle’s view that temperance is a way to
hit the mean. “Excess with regard to pleasures is self-indulgence and is
culpable; with regards to pains one is not, as in the case of courage, called
temperate for facing them or self-indulgent for not doing so, but the
self-indulgent man is so called because he is pained more than he ought at not
getting pleasant things… and the temperate man is so called because he is not
pained at the absence of what is pleasant and his abstinence from it.” (118b-25,
Ross) “These passages also indicate that temperance is medial, self-indulgence
is excess, and insensibility is deficiency… With respect to courage and
temperance, the two virtues Hursthouse discusses… Aristotle sometimes takes the
doctrine of the mean heuristically or metaphorically, but he gives no
indication of doing so in his accounts of courage and temperance. Here he takes
the mean to be straightforwardly quantitative. (Curzer, 132) According to
Curzer Aristotle accounts for a quantitative doctrine of the mean that is a
plausible picture of the virtues. Therefore, a quantitative interpretation
should be accepted over a metaphorical, heuristic one.
I
hold that if a doctrine of the mean is too demanding then it is not plausible.
Wolf backs my argument with her picture of the moral saints.”By moral saint I
mean a person whose every action is as morally good as possible, a person, that
is, who is as morally worthy as can be.” (Wolf, 419) She believes that this
moral saint is not an ideal person because this person must strive to be
morally perfect by helping everyone around them to be happy. Whether that
person does it out of a desire to be happy by making all others happy (loving
saint) or the person attaches a higher importance on everyone’s welfare above
their own (rational saint), this person loses out because they do not have time
for non-moral goods. Non-moral goods include personal likes of cooking,
watching basketball, or having a sarcastic sense of humor. “A moral theory that
does not contain the seeds of an all-consuming ideal of moral sainthood thus
seems to place false and unnatural limits on our opportunity to do some moral
good and our potential to deserve moral praise.” (Wolf, 433) Not only must this
person give up their own attachments to non-moral goods, but they also have to
have a high level of rationality to make everyone’s welfare better. Moral
saints must live like phronimos. They must hit the mean every time. Their
reasoning has to be precise. This precision attaches a level that seems to be
too demanding. Not everyone has the high intellectual level it would take to be
a phronimos. “Brannmark: “… the only way in which the phronimoi are extreme is
in their precision. Thus, while it might be difficult to live like a phronimos,
it is not the kind of difficulty involved in running marathons every day but
rather the kind of difficulty involved in hitting the bull’s eye all the time.”
(Wolf handout, 2) This level of rationality is not plausible. According to
Driver virtue must be accessible not to those that are wise, but to those that
are kind. Greatness of soul is another
virtue that makes the doctrine of the mean not plausible. The individual that
is considered a great soul is compared to the moral saint. It is viewed that
greatness of soul is the mean between vanity and smallness of soul. This virtue
is a crown to all the other virtues and all the virtues cannot exist without
it. Unless one has certain amount of external goods they cannot have greatness
of soul. Not everyone has the resources to attain such a virtue. One cannot
quantifiably attain the mean even though they meet the requirements of the
other virtues. Lacking in one of virtues robs the individual of the capability
to become greatness of soul. Individuals will therefore be restricted from
attaining greatness of soul. The doctrine of the mean is not plausible due to
the fore mentioned demandingness. This
argument directly attacks Curzer’s second premise that a quantitative doctrine
of the mean offers a plausible picture of the virtues.
Nussbaum
brings up this idea of virtue as a sphere that represents the context of a
people. Demandingness disappears due to people’s definition of what the virtues
are, and some of the virtue spheres can be dropped according to the societal
context. It is not necessary to hit the mean according to Aristotle’s
definition based upon a ancient Greek society because the virtues have now
become attainable through our society’s context. I am not convinced that this
line of argument does away with the doctrine of the mean because one must meet
the mean despite the context of a culture. Demandingness disappears in one
aspect of attainable virtues, but resides because the virtues that are
culturally acceptable still need a mean. Her argument only allows for the
greatness of soul virtue to change in context but not in quantity. I have shown
that the doctrine of the mean has such high level of demandingness that it
cannot be plausible.
There are
major problems with prior argument. First the account does not allow for a
moral sainthood that could be attainable, secondly there are artificial limits
on morality. The moral sainthood argument does not provide an answer; it
provides only a criticism of Curzer’s argument. The argument also allows for
the opportunity for one to choose non-moral goods over morality. How do we
decide what is best? Since there is no other answer presented it does not
discount the argument’s plausibility despite its demandingness. Aristotle seems
to answer the question. “And, if, further, virtue is more exact and better than
any art, as nature also is, then virtue must have the quality of aiming at the
intermediate.” (1106b13-1106b15) The doctrine of the mean is demanding but
still plausible because there is no solution to attaining virtue besides the
mean of two related vices. This argument deals precisely with prior argument’s
premise that if a doctrine is too demanding then it is not plausible.
The
prior argument seems to suggest that just because there is no other answer
presented that the doctrine of the mean must be correct. This cannot be true
because the answer to attaining virtues is an attainable. If something requires
impossible actions then that action is too demanding. The doctrine of the mean
requires impossible actions. The doctrine of the mean is too demanding. Through
previous parts of this paper I have shown that attaining phronesis, greatness
of soul, or moral sainthood requires impossible actions. Not everyone can have
the right rationality all of the time, they cannot attain greatness of soul if
they do not have certain amounts of external goods, nor can they attain moral
sainthood without phronesis. Because of these impossible demands the doctrine
of the mean is too demanding. This deals specifically with the premise that
demandingness is not a strong enough reason to do away with a doctrine. The only
answer known to a problem does not conclude that it is the correct or only
answer knowable.
The
doctrine of the mean is too demanding despite Curzer’s attempt to show that the
heuristic view of the Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean is silly and that the
precise use of the doctrine of the mean is a plausible way to interpret
Aristotle. I showed that demandingness puts virtue too far out of reach of the
majority of humans. Then I demonstrated that the doctrine of the mean can still
exist despite its demandingness. Then I responded by showing that impossible
actions are enough to determine whether something is too demanding. The
doctrine of the mean is too demanding.
Bibliography
1. Ross, David. The Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford University Press,
1980
2. Curzer, Howard. A Defense of
Aristotle’s Doctrine that Virtue Is a Mean. Mathesis Publications, 1996
3. Wolf, Susan. Moral Saints. The
Journal of Philosophy, 1982
4. Hursthouse, Rosalind. A False
Doctrine of the Mean. Blackwell Publishing, 1980
5. Nussbaum, Martha. Non-relative Virtues: An
Aristotelian Approach. Oxford University Press, 1993
No comments:
Post a Comment